Hashtag

At a time of defensive wars of aggression, what constitutes ethical violence?

  • Written by Hugh Breakey, Deputy Director, Institute for Ethics, Governance & Law. President, Australian Association for Professional & Applied Ethics., Griffith University
The Conversation

As the title suggests, Carlo Bordini’s Ethical Violence studies the ways different forms of violence – especially but not only, war – come to be accepted as morally legitimate.

The book builds on the Italian sociologist and journalist’s prior work examining social forces and changes unfolding in modern times.

For Bordoni, “ethical violence” is violence that, though dangerous, has become legitimised and accepted by a community as permissible or even necessary.

Review: Ethical Violence – Carlo Boldini (Polity)

Bordoni explores the horrors of Nazi Germany and considers the Russian invasion of Ukraine. While the book does not touch on the current conflagrations in the Middle East, these provide all-too-clear examples of brutality that is accepted and even celebrated by different sides.

People hold up placards at a demonstration in Israel featuring photos of the Israeli hostages held in Gaza.
Protesters in Jerusalem on January 22 hold placards and photos of missing people as they call for the immediate release of Israeli hostages held by Hamas in Gaza. Abir Sultan/EPA

It is a basic moral tenet and enduring concept in ethics that life is sacred and worthy of respect. So how might the known, intentional killing of thousands of human beings, such as in a war, be morally accepted? Or even seen as rational?

Bordoni surveys a myriad of hypotheses, traversing sociology, philosophy, political theory, history, legal theory and the social sciences. He brings into discussion thinkers as diverse as Friedrich Nietzsche, Max Weber, Michel Foucault, Carl Schmitt, Hannah Arendt, Steven Pinker and Zygmunt Bauman.

The German sociologist Weber, for instance, viewed war as a beneficial catalyst for change. German philosopher Georg Simmel speculated on war’s capacity to create valuable internal cohesion among nation states.

Sifting through various views, Bordoni reflects that even in a single case there may be multiple answers. Leaders may have rational reasons (moral or self-interested) for going to war. Yet solidarity, heightened emotion and even irrationality might also be required to ignite the popular will to wage war, with all its sacrifices and brutalities.

Read more: Israel-Palestinian conflict: is the two-state solution now dead?

Self defence

The late 20th century saw the fitful development of the view that wars must not be fought for a state’s general political or economic interests, but only in self-defence. As Bordoni observes, this shut the front door to war only to allow it in through the back. Today, he writes, “we only have defensive wars”.

The current conflagrations in the Middle East support Bordoni’s insight. Israel and Hamas, the United States and Yemen, Iran and Pakistan: all these very different conflicts are, in the eyes of those fighting them, defensive wars. Each side sees itself as justifiably responding to a past or present attack.

Even Russia dubiously justified its invasion of Ukraine by claiming it was defending citizens against “Nazis”, describing NATO’s expansion as “a serious provocation”.

The funeral of a Ukranian soldier and poet Maksym Kryvtsov killed in the war. People kneel as soldiers carry the coffin of Ukrainian soldier and poet Maksym Kryvtsov - killed by Russian troops - at his funeral on January 11. Efrem Lukatsky/AAP

Bordoni’s work helps us understand the many reasons why societies might adopt a war footing. It is less useful, though, in trying to think through the ethics of these conflicts, if by ethics we mean what we should do.

Bordoni suggests that if we truly acknowledged the ethical value of all human life (including that of our enemies), war would not be possible.

He draws on Judith Butler’s idea of “grievability”, where communities determine whose deaths are appropriately mourned. Some lives will not be seen as valued and their deaths not worthy of grieving. If all lives were recognised as grievable, Bordoni argues, it would be impossible to accept war’s human costs.

Read more: Friday essay: 'what else should I lose to survive?' The young writers living – and dying – in Gaza

But Bordoni’s argument here seems flawed on two important counts.

First, it is not necessary to dehumanise someone to decide they must be killed. It is entirely possible to cleave to a moral principle – such as everyone’s right to life – and at the same time to neutralise the principle’s applicability in the present case.

This can be done in selective and hypocritical ways. Our ingenious human brains can confect reasons why this case is an exception to a rule we otherwise righteously acknowledge. Russia’s invasion of Ukraine presents a plausible example. Russia never claimed state sovereignty was meaningless or Ukrainian citizens deserve to be slaughtered. Instead, its claims about Nazis and NATO sought to show the Ukrainian context created an exception to the widely accepted prohibition on military aggression.

Bombed apartment buildings in Bucha Ukraine. A bombed housing estate in Bucha Ukraine, in April 2022. Maca Vojtech Darvik/AAP

Second, there is one case where that “exception” does seem justified, namely, in genuine cases of self-defence. Most contemporary ethical thought – in particular “just war theory” – allows the use of war, and even collateral damage, in self defence against aggressors.

This is an important point: “ethical violence” is not merely a sociological process of building popular legitimacy for mass violence (Bordoni’s focus). It is also the demand to temper our violence until it can pass ethical muster. This involves providing strictures on when actions like war are permissible (the “jus ad bellum” of just war theory). It also requires respecting laws like the Geneva Conventions and the Genocide Convention, that protect civilians during war (the “jus in bello”).

Read more: How should we think about war? Understanding Just War Theory

Still, a counter argument here is that, while genuine claims of self-defence are pivotal in ethical decisions to visit violence on others, it may be that the social and psychological weight of actually inflicting the brutal violence demanded by war requires a dehumanised and hated foe.

If this is the case, even the most justified war carries a profound moral risk. We must demean the enemy, seeing human beings as obstacles requiring elimination, rather than intrinsic sources of value.

People search a bombed out building for survivors in Rafah, Gaza. Palestinians search for survivors of an Israeli bombing in Rafah, Gaza Strip, in November, 2023. Hatem Ali/AP

Modernity and mass violence

How is it that modernity – since the Enlightenment – has not consigned war and terrorism to the barbaric past? Bordoni develops a complex picture of modernity – or rather modernities, following Israeli sociologist Shmuel Eisenstadt in seeing a series of sociological and economic upheavals over recent centuries. These included the creation of state sovereignty, the rise of reason and science, industrialisation and the proliferation of technology.

To these we must add the crises of modernity in recent decades, with its values of progress, human equality and rationality being questioned.

Bordoni sees our current times as characterised by a push back against rationality and science, with the embrace of emotions (including resentment). We take rationality for granted, he warns, but in truth it is a cultural achievement – a “precious plant”.

Even so, Bordoni cautions against the comfortable view the excesses of 20th century violence were departures from modernity. For modernity promises an orderly, standardised world, governed and controlled by precise rules to achieve conformity, security, safety and prosperity. This demand for control and perfection characterises the totalitarian impulse. Totalitarianism inevitably produces enormous violence.

The cover of Ethical Violence Goodreads Bordoni’s book is intellectually refreshing in its willingness to marshal many different ideas and to resist definitively choosing one theory or approach over another. But this very feature can make Ethical Violence a challenging and at times frustrating read. The book doesn’t have a central driving thesis or overarching argument the author systematically pursues. Many ideas are raised, briefly discussed, then left aside. Bordoni’s sociological and historical approach helps the reader stand back from the headlines to consider the modern world’s large-scale structures and disruptions. He gathers disparate threads together meaningfully, allowing us to recognise key changes and see our present moment anew: a time when, he suggests, technology is trusted but science is not and emotion and individuality have superseded rationality and competence. Yet there are worries with this broad-brush approach. A focus on the differences across generations and centuries can obscure the continuities. It can also simplify. After all, in every era there are dissenting voices and rival movements. Modern societies – like, perhaps, all societies – have threads of rationality and irrationality, domains where emotion is praised and times when it is repressed. As a result, a very different story of modernity could be told, arguing modernity actually represents the dawning awareness we must relinquish control and divide power. After all, modernity gave us the toleration valorised by Locke and Voltaire. The distrust of government that delivered the US Constitution. The elaboration of the separation of powers and democratic accountability. John Stuart Mill’s celebration of human diversity. And the creation of institutions (such as the United Nations), developed not to build heaven on earth, but merely to save us from hell. Read more: Criticism of Western Civilisation isn't new, it was part of the Enlightenment A sweeping work In Bordoni’s book, “ethical violence” is a recurring theme rather than a singular focus. He engages in many intriguing discussions. It is impossible in a review to even mention the myriad ideas he raises. Indeed, in the book’s final chapter, the topic of ethical violence is entirely left behind, as Bordoni ruminates on technology, science, rationality, human individuality, loneliness and alienation. Still, Ethical Violence is a valuable book for those who want their thinking to be challenged and enriched, to reflect on the modern condition, and to consider where we might all be heading. Authors: Hugh Breakey, Deputy Director, Institute for Ethics, Governance & Law. President, Australian Association for Professional & Applied Ethics., Griffith University

Read more https://theconversation.com/at-a-time-of-defensive-wars-of-aggression-what-constitutes-ethical-violence-220221

Health & Wellness

How to Maintain Your Oral Health During Stressful Times

Hashtag.net.au - avatar Hashtag.net.au

Life can be a bit like an Australian outback road—full of twists, turns, and the occasional bump. During these hectic, stressful times, it’s all too easy to let your oral health fall by the wayside...

The impact of visual art on mental health and productivity

Hashtag.net.au - avatar Hashtag.net.au

In a world where stress and anxiety often take center stage, the presence of visual art in our daily environments offers a quiet yet profound counterbalance. Posters and paintings are not just decor...

Understanding the Environmental and Health Impacts of Waste Disposal: Essential Insights

Hashtag.net.au - avatar Hashtag.net.au

🌎♻️Explore the health & environmental impacts of waste disposal. Dive into essential insights💡for a sustainable future! #WasteManagement #Health🌿🌍 Waste disposal is an inevitable aspect of mode...